Connect tradition and progress |
„Methodenstreit“ and Political
Science
The
Methodological Science War
at the Beginning of the 21st Century between
the
scientistic Establishment and phronetic Perestroicans
|
|
|
|
1. Introduction:
Methodology and Political Science
Other files in English:
|
|
|
|
|
1.1 Starting
points: methodological disputes within political science, past and present |
|
1.1.1 Relevance and instrumental nature of methodology for
science |
|
The central relevance of scientific methodology lies in the fact that
methodology alone establishes and legitimizes a demarcation line between
science and other forms of cognition. Science is the place where scientific
knowledge is generated. In antiquity, methodology undergirded the
transition from myth to logos, and still today it makes it possible to
distinguish between scientific knowledge and other forms of knowledge that are not
scientifically, i.e. not methodologically and not systematically,
generated.
Methodology is both the tool and the object of science. As a tool, it
serves to generate content in the form of knowledge. Methodology itself is
also the subject of scientific research, critically evaluated and developed
further. Methodology delimits the boundaries of “science”. Note that the
terms “knowledge” and “science” really belong together. In other languages
(except in Latin, where the word “scientia” means both science and
knowledge) this is not as obvious as in German, where we have Wissenschaft
(science) and Wissen (knowledge): for example, there are two words in
English, “science” and “knowledge”, and in French “science” and “savoir” or
“connaissances”. Scientists therefore generate knowledge within scientific
institutions with the help of various scientific tools. So the scientific
methodology establishes a demarcation line between scientific knowledge and
other forms of scientific knowledge. However, this line is constantly shifting due to
the methodological developments, and indeed the limits of knowledge are
ceaselessly widening or narrowing.
But in each individual field, methodology also plays a role in aspects
other than knowledge generation. It is involved in the training and
socialization of professional representatives, in recruitment to scientific
institutes, and, later, in the promotion of research, for example in the
allocation of research funds in scientific institutes or in enabling
publications: “What becomes clear in this context is the extent to which
methods currently serve as identity markers for various fields, including
as gatekeepers for doctoral students embarking on comprehensive exams and
dissertation research, graduating PhDs seeking jobs, junior faculty seeking
promotion and tenure, and all seeking research funding, opportunities to
present work in conferences, and publications outlets for research. And the
issues arise as well in teaching, curricular design, and textbooks
contents” (Yanow/Schwartz-Shea
2014a [2006]: 421-422). The methodology thus leads internally to the
emergence of schools and of professional boundaries. Rejecting these
disputes as fetishism would mean obscuring the various actual or alleged
incommensurabilities between different academic schools and traditions as
well as the constructed individual and professional identities.
So, methodology basically has two different meanings. The endogenous
significance of methodology lies in distinguishing scientifically
legitimized knowledge from other forms of knowledge. The exogenous
importance of methodology governs the socialization and co-optation of new
members in the science system, further contributing to the promotion of
research and the development of society.
I have nothing said about the relevance of, for example, lifeworld,
religious or ideological forms of knowledge generation; they are neither
appraised nor devalued. The pejorative devaluation as “pseudoscience” of
findings that are not reached by following the methodological requirements
of a school, for instance in Critical Rationalism, is widespread. Findings
of scientists from other schools are also subsumed under pseudoscience.
Furthermore, within methodological studies the value of science cannot be
discussed, and arguments for or against a scientification of politics
cannot be examined.
This study discusses the instrumental character of methodology for the
generation and legitimation of knowledge (endogenous meaning). Its
relevance to the socialization of researchers and the promotion of research
(exogenous importance) is not addressed.
|
1.1.2 Foundations of scientific research: axiology,
epistemology, methodology and ontology |
|
Epistemology, methodology, and ontology constitute the “sacred trinity”
of science, which is particularly addressed within the philosophy of
science: “‘[M]ethodology’ often appears as one member in a trio of the
philosophy of science, the two other being ‘ontology’ and ‘epistemology’.
These are the three musketeers of metaphysics” (Moses/Knutsen
2012 [2007]: 4). For the individual sciences, the methodology, in
particular the methodical level (Chart
1), is the favorite child, while epistemology is accepted as a
necessary evil. Ontology is clearly the stepchild and was often dismissed
as obsolete by many (neo-) positivist and naturalistic philosophers of
science or scientists in the individual sciences, especially in the 20th
century. Since the 1990s, this has been changing very slowly, including in
political science (Hay
2011 [2009]).
Jonathon W. Moses and Torbjørn L. Knutsen analyze epistemological,
methodological and ontological issues in terms of their relevance to
political science research and, above all, consider them with epistemic
glasses. In their book, “Ways of Knowing. Competing Methodologies in Social
and Political Research” (Moses/Knutsen
2012 [2007]), this is clearly noticeable in the structure and the
discussion. Moses and Knutsen try to objectively represent both positions,
they speak of naturalism versus constructivism; that is, both the
possibilities and the limitations of the two methodologies are analyzed.
Their second important goal is to build methodological bridges (Moses/Knutsen
2012 [2007]: 302) between naturalism and constructivism.
Axiological questions are just as relentlessly discussed in the
“Methodenstreit”. Therefore, in some methodology books they are quite rightly
cited alongside epistemological, methodological and ontological questions (Creswell
2013 [1998]: 21). The main issue is whether there is a separation between
“is” and “ought” (Sein and Sollen). Scientistic scientists affirm this by
referring to Weber (2011
[1904] and
1973e [1919]), while interpretivists and perestroikans deny this. Furthermore, the question of to what
extent value-laden (scientific) research exists or how values influence
research as knowledge-guiding interests (Habermas
1968c) remains controversial. In general, axiological questions are about
how to deal with questions of value and what role practical questions
should play.
The scientistic scientists, who also operate under other names, such as
social scientists, naturalists, positivists, or neo-positivists,
concentrate primarily on the methodical level in the narrower sense (Chart
1) and treat the philosophical foundations rather as a stepmother.
These questions, which were in the foreground in the second half of the
19th and the first half of the 20th century, have been pushed into the
background. At the forefront came arguments at the methodical level, more
precisely between the representatives of quantitative and qualitative
research.
The importance of the philosophical level is again emphasized not only by the
phronetic perestroikans but also by the interpretivists: “Treating methods
as self-standing ‘tools’ apart from the pre-supposed ontological and
epistemological positions that inform and shape them and their themes” (Yanow/Schwartz-Shea
2014a [2006]: 425,
Bevir 2010 [2008],
Moses/Knutsen
2012 [2007],
Bevir/Rhodes 2016a,
Bevir/Blakely
2016).
In this work, the emphasis is on methodology rather than the methods
level, so that all issues are considered through philosophical
(axiological, epistemic, methodological and ontological) glasses. All
questions are discussed on ten vertical levels (Chart
1) and on three horizontal levels (Chart
2).
|
1.1.3 The Aristotelian Organon: possibilities and limitations
of scientific methodology |
|
Plato and Aristotle can be described as the two founding fathers of political
science. This applies both to content-related questions of the field as well as
to the rather formal, methodological questions that are the subject of this
work. Aristotle enjoys a higher reputation among empirically-oriented political
scientists.
From a methodological point of view, Aristotle’s Organon (Aristotle
1920 [4th century BC], Aristotle:
https://archive.org/details/AristotleOrganon) can be considered the
first book on methodology. In it, Aristotle systematically discussed all
rational or scientific tools with which the leap from myth to logos was
made in ancient times – impartial, objective and factual, sine ira et
studio. He explored in particular the possibilities and limits of
scientific methodology or of tools in the broader sense (axiological,
epistemic and ontological conditions) as well as in the narrower sense
(categories, logic (syllogism), dialectics, rhetoric).
|
1.1.4 Extensive methodological discourses and an unmanageable
variety of scientific tools |
|
Today, in the early decades of the 21st
century, we have an unmanageable variety of scientific tools (concepts,
propositions, theories, logics, argumentations, methods and methodological
approaches) and of discourses on the foundations of scientific methodology,
theory and prerequisites for scientific work (e.g. on tasks, limits,
assumptions, criteria and characteristics of scientific research), both within
the philosophy of science and within the social sciences, not least – or
especially – in political science. Several different approaches, as well as
attitudes, can be observed in political science at the start of the 21st
century:
- A. ignorance of methodological questions, “just do it” pragmatics
- B. methodological grunt work in normal mode within different
methodological traditions and schools
- C. methodological wars in revolutionary mode
- D. pluralistic habitus and reductionist practices.
A. Ignorance of methodological questions, “just do it” pragmatics
Since the emergence of modern social sciences, methodological questions have
been regarded by many empirical scientists as a necessary evil, if not as
superfluous. Probably the vast majority of political scientists hold a pragmatic
attitude (“just do it”) coupled with an ignorance of methodological questions:
“Their motto is, once again: ‘just do it’ (Barry 1970, v; Dryzek 2005)” (Goodin
2011b [2009]: 29). Goodin also states: “But the vast majority of political
scientists whose main concern is generally nonplussed. They do so in the same
way they would have done under any alternate regime” (Goodin
2011b [2009]: 30-31).
Those who wish to extol the virtues of this attitude can, however unfoundedly,
even quote a classic such as Weber: “All this gives rise to the wish that the
current fashion for every beginner’s work to be adorned with epistemological
inquiries will very soon die out”, my translation: “[D]ies alles läßt den Wunsch
entstehen, es möge die heutige Mode, daß jede Anfängerarbeit mit
erkenntnistheoretischen Untersuchungen geziert werden muß, recht bald wieder
aussterben” (Weber
1973b [1903-1906]: 127). This remark referred to a footnote to Dr. Biermann.
Weber is considered a classic in the social sciences, because he made lasting
contributions to the methodology of the social sciences, and also because he
implemented the methodological guidelines in his empirical work. One should
therefore not overestimate these critical remarks and pay close attention to the
context of their creation and use.
B. Methodological grunt work in normal mode within different
methodological traditions and schools
“Normal” methodological grunt work takes place within different
methodological traditions, or in schools within these traditions; without this
work, the enormous methodological progress of the last century would not have
been possible. The platonic-galilean tradition, which maintains a methodological
reductionism and is very homogeneous, is usually introduced first. This is
followed by the aristotelian tradition, which represents a methodological
pluralism and is very heterogeneous. Only one school from the aristotelian
tradition, the perestroikans, is discussed in detail in this work. The
distinction made between the platonic-galilean and the aristotelian tradition,
or in other words between methodological reductionism and methodological
pluralism, builds on the work of Georg Henrik
von Wright
(1971) and was further developed by me elsewhere (Lauer
2013).
“The Oxford Handbook of Political Methodology” (Box-Steffensmeier/Brady/Collier,
2010a [2008], hereinafter referred to as “Political Methodology”) currently
offers the most outstanding overview of the platonic-galilean tradition.
The naturalistic, positivist, or scientistic methodology of the discipline
is oriented towards the natural sciences, understands as part of the social
sciences and works above all with experiments, logical-mathematical
argumentation methods, quantitative and qualitative-mathematical
(qualitative positivistic) methods as well as with models (in particular
rational choice models).
There has been criticism of this scientistic, platonic-galilean tradition
since the 19th century from scholars
leaning on the humanities, on human sciences, or on linguistic, hermeneutic,
(post) structuralist or interpretative lines of argumentation as well as on
preferred qualitative-interpretative methods and methodological approaches (Dilthey
1922 [1883],
Rothacker 1926,
Rickert 1910 [1896],
Windelband 1900 [1894],
Gadamer 2010
[1960],
Garfinkel (1967),
Glaser/Strauss
1967, Foucault 1971
[1966 ] and
1995 [1969],
Geertz 1983 [1973]),
Giddens (1984 [1976]), Bodammer
1987,
Denzin/Lincoln 1994,
Creswell 2013 [1998],
Flick/von
Kardorff/Steinke 2015 [2000],
Blatter/Janning/Wagemann
2007,
Yanow/Schwartz-Shea
2014 [2006], Bevir/Rhodes
2016a).
At the beginning of the 21st
century, a new methodological school within the aristotelian tradition stood up
in opposition to the scientistic, naturalistic methodology. This school sees
itself as a phronetic political or social science (Flyvbjerg
2001 and
2006,
Schram/Caterino 2006)
or as real social science (Flyvbjerg/ Landman/Schram
2012a). The phronetic scientists take arguments from the aristotelian tradition,
but they are also part of the perestroika movement and argue for an independent,
real social science. An overview of the diversity of the perestroika movement is
provided in the book “Perestroika! The Raucous Rebellion in Political Science” (Monroe
2005). This book also presents an evaluation of the movement. A further
evaluation followed in Perspectives on Politics in 2015 (Gunnel
2015a and
2015b,
Farr 2015,
Laitin 2015,
Monroe 2015 and
Schram 2015).
It must be emphasized that the “normal”, grunt work is almost
exclusively done within the two traditions. The representatives of these
two traditions usually do not engage in constructive engagement with
representatives of the other tradition: instead, their respective grunt
work leads them to an unproductive methodological war.
C. Methodological war in revolutionary mode. The opponents in the
“Methodenstreit” within political science at the start of the 21st
century: scientistic political scientists versus phronetic perestroikans
Disputes within political science can inflame into religious wars with
Manichean features, as Klaus Gustav Heinrich von
Beyme (2000 [1972]: 142) diagnoses. He was referring to the methodological
disputes during the so-called “behavioral revolution” in the 1950s and 1960s and
the “rational choice revolution” in the 1970s. Today religious wars within
science have unfortunately not disappeared. Robert Edward Goodin, a
representative of the scientistic establishment, also notes in his “State of the
Discipline, the Discipline of the State” that disputes within political science
often take a “Manichean, Good versus Evil Form” (Goodin
2011b [2009]: 10). Unfortunately, this also applies to the arguments about the
adequate methodology.
The scientistic scientists (Chart
3) assume that their counterparts cannot work scientifically: “American
scientists, however, often have reduced all the competing approaches [all
approaches except the rational choice approach] to the status of inferior
journalism”, my translation: „Amerikanische Wissenschaftler haben aber
vielfach alle konkurrierenden Ansätze [gemeint sind hier alle Ansätze außer dem
Rational-Choice-Ansatz] auf den Status eines inferioren Journalismus
herabgedrückt“ (von Beyme
2000 [1972]: 148). In the same vein, the disciplined political scientists also
work with other, subtler insults: colleagues are not regarded as scientists, but
only as theorists. Furthermore, these theoreticians, who are also described as
happy and undisciplined, are not classified as being within the scientific
departments of the social science faculties, but in the humanities: “Political
theory is an interdisciplinary endeavor whose center of gravity lies at the
humanities end of the happily still undisciplined discipline of political
science”(Dryzek/Honig/Philips
2009: 62; see ibidem political scientist versus political theorist p. 63).
The rejection and devaluation of other axiological, epistemic and
ontological assumptions as well as methodological procedures is the
strategy of the scientistic scientist in this scientific war. Second, there
is also a rejection or at least a devaluation of linguistic-hermeneutical
or philological-interpretive arguments, methods and methodological
approaches. “Political science is the only social science in which the
history of past theories plays a special role. ‘History of dogma’ in
economics, on the other hand, became a secondary subject for ‘fairy tale
examinations’ – in addition to the hard business of quantifying economics”,
my translation: „Die Politikwissenschaft ist die einzige Sozialwissenschaft, in der die
Geschichte vergangener Theorien eine besondere Rolle spielt. ‚Dogmengeschichte‘
in der Ökonomie wurde dagegen zum Nebenfach für ‚Märchenklausuren‘ – neben dem
harten Geschäft der quantifizierenden Ökonomie“ (von Beyme
2002: 14).
This subdivision is especially strong in economics, but it goes to the
heart of a division that also exists in political science, especially in
the United States. Just as economic history tends to be investigated in the
history departments, scientistic political scientists also try to deport
the history of ideas, political philosophy, and generally all
“theoreticians” who work “only” with linguistic-interpretive methods of
argumentation and qualitative-interpretative methods, into the humanities.
Only those who look for causalities may claim the status of “scientist”.
The opponents of the scientistic scientists (the humanities and cultural
scientists, constructivists, anti-positivists, hermeneutics, interpreters,
structuralists or post-structuralists, phronetic perestroikans, human
scientists; Chart 4), in
turn, react with exaggerated and in part unjustified criticism. While it is true
that the scientists often do not take their opponents seriously or ignore them
altogether, the interpretivists tend to build up straw men that they can then
easily knock down. Not only do they reject the positivist and naturalistic
assumptions for exploring the political and social world, but they also deem the
logical-mathematical tools to be unsuitable. These are, in essence, the main
arguments for the demand for a turnaround in human and social sciences and the
necessity of a post-positive political science.
Furthermore, they point in particular to the alleged lack of public relevance
(Flyvbjerg, 2001),
method-driveness (Green/Shapiro 1994) or unworldly self-centeredness in the form of methodological
scholasticism (Mead 2010). It is not surprising, then, that Bent Flyvbjerg, one
of the representatives of the perestroika movement (Flyvbjerg
2006: 56), speaks of a “science war” (Flyvbjerg
2001: 1).
The dispute, which has now degenerated into a methodological war,
emerged in the nineteenth century because of the orientation of some
scientists in the social sciences towards the natural sciences, and others’
rejection of such aspirations.
The Kuhn narrative, i.e. the use of the philosophy of science of Thomas
Samuel Kuhn
(1962) to explain progress within the sciences, has acted like a fire
accelerator, since both sides use it not only to prove their own superiority but
also to present their opponents as being outdated. Thus, a meaningful debate
between scientists with different theoretical assumptions becomes fundamentally
impossible from the outset.
It is astonishing to witness scientists go from “normal” academics to
religious warriors when they act as revolutionary standard-bearers. They then
have only one goal: to kill all methodological opponents by all available means.
In my opinion, a drive for money or power can also be identified in the
revolutionary mode, because scientists are also always fighting for
material resources to gain recognition, publication and career
opportunities. This is largely the case because the existential,
socio-economic situation of the overwhelming majority of political
scientists has been very precarious since the emergence of the field.
Already at the start of the twentieth century, Weber spoke in his
well-known speech “Science as a Vocation” of the fact that
the situation of many scholars and scientists in Germany, just as in the
USA, was “as precarious as any proletarian existence”, my translation:
“ähnlich prekär wie jede ‘proletaroide’ Existenz” (Weber
1973e [1919]: 584 [526]). Aristotle, on the other hand, did not personally
face such existential or economic problems.
“If social science were viewed less as a prizefight between competing
theoretical perspectives, only one of which may prevail, and more as a
joint venture in which explanations condition and augment another, the
partisan impulses that give rise to methodologically deficient research
might be held in check” (Green/Shapiro 1994: 204). Unfortunately, this call from the last century has remained a
pious wish, as the methodological war at the start of the 21st century
between the scientistic scientists ((King/Keohane/Verba
1994,
Brady/Collier
2010 [2004], Box-Steffensmeier/Brady/Collier
2010a [2008]) and the phronetic perestroikans (Flyvbjerg
2001,Schram/Caterino
2006,
Flyvbjerg/Landman/Schram
2012a), the interpreters (Rosenthal
2014 [2005],
Kleemann/Krähnke/Matuschek
2009, Yanow/Schwartz-Shea
2014 [2006],
Bevir/Rhodes
2016a,
Münch 2016) or the qualitative
researchers (Denzin/Lincoln
1994,
Creswell 2013 [1998],
Flick/von
Kardorff/Steinke 2015 [2000],
Blatter/Janning/Wagemann
2007) attests.
Because these argumentations are delivered in revolutionary mode, there are
many misunderstandings, whereas sober, rational discussions would bring the
parties closer. The polarizing approach to methodological questions within the
social sciences differs very clearly and unfavorably from Aristotle’s approach.
This is not only borne out by the violence of the words “Methodenstreit”,
"Positivismusstreit" (Adorno
1976, Falter 1982,
Keuth 1989,
Topitsch 1967), or “science
war” (Flyvbjerg 2001:
1). Since the first methodological disputes in the 19th century arose in the
German-speaking world, the word "Methodenstreit" has found its way into the
English language, where it is still used today quite idiosyncratically, in lower
case and grammatically incorrectly: “[H]arking back to the method dispute” (Hawkesworth
2006: 152). Other Anglo-Saxon authors also use the German word (Caterino/Schram
2006: 11).
D. Pluralistischer Habitus und reduktionistische Praktiken
Pluralism is a value that hardly a political scientist calls into question
today, even if, like the scientistic and phronetic reductionists, they practice
exactly the opposite. In short, the adversaries in this methodological war
constantly display a pluralistic habitus, even if they daily pursue or
implement a reductionist agenda.
The tendency to a camp mentality is rejected beyond the boundaries of
one’s own camp (Green/Shapiro 1994: 204). The tendency of others to debate in an either-or-mode is
constantly lamented. This is true not only of the two great disputes, the
one the Neo-Marxists (Caucus for a new Political Science) began in the
1960s and 1970s and the one the perestroikans started in the early 21st
century, but also of many other disputes: “[T]here is a remarkable penchant
for representing the options in ‘either-or’ fashion. Behavioralist or
traditionalist, structure or agency, ideas or interests, realist or
idealist, rationalist or interpretivist: you simply have to choose, so we
are constantly told. On all those dimensions and many others as well, the
only proper response is to refuse to choose. Respond insistently, ‘Both!’”
(Goodin
2011b [2009]: 10). Goodin also conceded that the perestroikans propagate a
pluralistic ideology: “This is the official ideology, if not always
practice, of the perestroika movement” (Goodin
2011b [2009]: 10, footnote 19 with reference to
Schram 2003: 837).
However, this pluralistic aim is not always applied in the eleven-volume
series “The Oxford Handbook of Political Science” (Goodin
2011a [2009]), which was supervised by Goodin as general editor. In particular,
the volume “Political Methodology” (Box-Steffensmeier/Brady/Collier
2010a [2008]), which is most relevant to this investigation, practices
methodological reductionism: only the logical-mathematical methodology is
presented in detail. The linguistic-interpretive methodology for the
interpretation of meaning-making or sense-making is completely ignored. In this
volume, the declared aim of which is to provide an overview of the entire
methodology of political science, only methodologies that apply causal thinking
are included. Qualitative-mathematical methods are explained, but no
qualitative-interpretative methods, although there a wealth of such methods has
been used for decades (Denzin/Lincoln
1994,
Flick/von Kardorff/Steinke
2015 [2000],
Blatter/Janning/Wagemann
2007,
Creswell
2013 [1998],
Yanow/Schwartz-Shea
2014 [2006],
Bevir/Rhodes
2016a).
On the other side, Bent Flyvbjerg
(2001) also justifies his plea for a phronetic, real social science in part by
pointing to the fundamental difference between natural and social sciences.
Furthermore, he does not tire of emphasizing the practical insignificance or
irrelevance of quantitative methodology, uncovering the limits of deductive
reasoning and propounding the superiority of inductive reasoning.
At the end of the first part of his book, he suddenly states: “To
amputate one side in these pairs of phenomena into a dualistic ‘either-or’
is to amputate our understanding. Rather than the ‘either-or’, we should
develop a non-dualistic and pluralistic ‘both-and’. Hence, we should not
criticize rules, logic, signs, and rationality in themselves. We should
criticize only the dominance of these phenomena to the exclusion of others
in modern society and in social science. Conversely, it would be equally
problematic if rules, logic, signs, and rationality where marginalized by
the concrete, by difference, and by the particular. This later problem,
however, is presently far less pressing than the former” (Flyvbjerg
2001: 49). One then wonders, why the plea for a phronetic revolution, which
supposedly alone can enable only a real social science? Would a simple
adjustment not have sufficed?
|
This work looks at three extensive questions:
1.2.1 The “Methodenstreit” or the methodological war
within political science
- Who are the protagonists in the methodological war?
- Which different axiological, epistemic, methodological or
ontological conditions or approaches do the protagonists prefer?
- What are the most important concepts and issues in the
"Methodenstreit" at the beginning of the 21st century?
- What shortcomings and misunderstandings determine the debate?
- Which concepts and procedures are best suited to reconstruct the
development of methodology?
1.2.2 Overcoming the methodological war
- How can the methodological war be overcome?
- What effects do axiology, epistemology and ontology have on methodology?
- Which philosophical (axiological, epistemic and ontological) assumptions can be partially identified as implicit assumptions within the methodology?
- What does a methodological differentiation look like on three horizontal and ten vertical levels?
- Can structural differences be found between empirical-interpretive (descriptive), empirical-scientistic (explanatory and prognostic) and practical (normative, pragmatic and technical) methodologies at different levels?
- Is there a complementarity between empirical-interpretive (descriptive), empirical-scientific (explanatory and prognostic) and practical (normative, pragmatic and technical) methodologies? Or, in other words:
- AAre empirical-interpretative, explanative-prognostical and practical methodologies contrary or complementary to each other?
1.2.3 Value issues within political science and practical methodology
- What are the main axiological differences or practical disputes
about questions of value in political science?
- What are the possibilities and limits of the practical
methodologies represented by scientistic scientists (normative rational
choice theory) and phronetic perestroikans (applied phronesis)?
-
Can a genuinely practical (normative, pragmatic and technical)
methodology include applied methodology (normative rational choice
approach) and problem-oriented methodology (applied phronesis)?
- Can a genuinely practical (normative, pragmatic and technical)
methodology establish the foundations for practical political science
as part of a “practical social science” (Weber 2011[1904]: 56)?
|
The following goals are pursued in this monograph:
- 1.3.1 “Methodenstreit” or methodological war within political
science: First, the “Methodenstreit” is presented. The discussion focuses
on the protagonists in the methodological war and the associated Kuhn
narrative and its terminology. The deficits, misunderstandings and issues that
arise are demonstrated with the help of an ad fontes reconstruction based on
original sources. Furthermore, a more appropriate terminology is presented,
with the help of which one can better reconstruct the development of political
methodology.
- 1.3.2 Overcoming the methodological war: Secondly, it is shown that
due to the complexity of the topic, it is necessary and sensible to explain
the crucial questions (axiological, epistemic, methodological or ontological)
on ten vertical and three horizontal levels. Only through an increase in
complexity can the counter-productive dispute transform into a constructive
discussion of the limits and possibilities of political methodology. Firstly,
the structural differences between empirical-interpretive (descriptive),
empirical-scientific (explanatory and prognostic) and practical (normative,
pragmatic and technical) methodologies are demonstrated. Then it is shown that
they are complementary. Due to this complementarity, mutual recognition
instead of religious war, and thus a constructive discussion, is possible.
- 1.3.3 Value issues within political science and practical methodology:
Third, I will build on the state of methodological knowledge within political
science with my own methodological considerations (Lauer
2013 and
1997).
Above all, I will point out the methodological deficits of the current
practical methodology, that of normative rational choice theory and applied
phronesis. Then I will explain the need for a genuinely practical (normative,
pragmatic and technical) methodology, since this differs in principle from an
empirical (descriptive, explanatory and prognostic) methodology on ten
methodological levels. Such a practical methodology can form the foundations
of practical political science as part of a “practical social science” (Weber
2011 [1904]: 56). Furthermore, important axiological questions such as the
influence of value questions on scientific results or the relationship between
politics and science will be discussed.
|
1.3.1 “Methodenstreit”: terminology, deficits, counterparties,
misunderstandings and issues in the methodological war, the scientistic
and the phronetic Kuhn narrative |
|
At the center of the work lies the philosophical (axiological,
epistemological, methodological and ontological) science war or
"Methodenstreit" within political science that erupted at the start of the 21st
century between the scientistic establishment and the phronetic perestroikans.
The emphasis on methodology does not justify excluding axiological, epistemic
and ontological questions; on the contrary, without discussing these questions
one cannot adequately discuss the science war because such questions decisively
influence the methodological approach.
This methodological war has been smoldering since the 19th
century, causing opponents to talk past each other rather than to each
other. The other side’s positions are simply ignored (scientistic
scientists), or the constant methodological developments of the other party
are not adequately perceived (interpretivists). The latter create straw men
that they then easily knock down.
The notion of ad fontes reconstruction was established in the
16th century by Desiderius
Erasmus of Rotterdam (1466-1536), Philipp Melanchthon (1497-1560) and
Martin Luther (1483-1546) as a humanistic tradition. It seeks to legitimize
scientific narratives with the help of original sources. This established
tradition in the humanities and in cultural studies is paradoxically
ignored by scientists who prefer linguistic-interpretive methods. The aim
of this monograph is to reconstruct the positions of the scientistic
scientists on the basis of scientific handbooks and their classics.
Both sides in the methodological war refer to the philosophy of science
of Thomas Samuel
Kuhn (1962),
so that I speak of two versions of the Kuhn narrative: a scientistic and a
phronetic version. However, the Kuhn narrative cannot adequately explain
the preceding methodological development. This narrative is
counterproductive, because it acts like a fire accelerator and contributes
decisively to the many misunderstandings in the dispute. It will be shown
that the concepts of Georg Henrik
von Wright (1971) and Imre
Lakatos (1978) are
better suited to represent the development of scientific methodology since
the emergence of science.
|
1.3.2 Overcoming the „Methodenstreit”:
axiological, epistemological, methodological and ontological aspects of
the methodological war on ten vertical and three horizontal levels |
|
A. Partizipative Wissenschaftsphilosophie
“Philosophy is like a lame man who cannot move without his crutches, the
sciences. And the sciences are like workers in the dark if they do not use the
light of philosophy to see the ways that connect them with life”, my
translation: “Die *Philosophie ist wie ein Lahmer, der ohne seine Stützen, die
*Wissenschaften, nichts bewegen kann. Und die *Wissenschaften sind wie Arbeiter
im Dunkeln, wenn sie nicht das Licht der *Philosophie benutzen, um die Wege zu
sehen, die sie mit dem Leben verbinden” (Lorenzen1974:
130). Although Lorenzen exaggerates the importance of the philosophical usually formal analyses are greatly underestimated,
while contributions by philosophers are generally overestimated. This also
applies analogously within the sciences.
Firstly, Lorenzen overestimates the possibilities of philosophy;
secondly, he usually pursues a philosophy of science in philosophy-of mode
rather than in philosophy-with mode. “In this mode [philosophy-of mode],
philosophers remain largely outside of the individual sciences with their
work. To this Hansson contrasts ‘philosophy with ...’, meaning a mode of
philosophizing in close collaboration with scientists from a particular
science. In this mode, philosophers of science do not operate as outsiders,
as observers of the individual sciences, but are themselves active
participants in the theory development process of the individual sciences.
In this perspective, the goal of the philosophy of science is not only to
understand what science is and, if possible, methodologically to improve
the science operation. Rather, a contribution to the individual scientific
questions should also be provided”, my translation: “In diesem Modus
[Philosophie-von-Modus] bleiben Philosophen mit ihrer Arbeit weitgehend
außerhalb der Einzelwissenschaften. Dem stellt Hansson die ‚Philosophie mit
…’ gegenüber, womit er einen Modus des Philosophierens in enger
Zusammenarbeit mit Fachwissenschaftlern aus einer Einzelwissenschaft meint.
In diesem Modus betreiben Wissenschaftsphilosophen ihr Fach nicht als
Außenstehende, als Beobachter der Einzelwissenschaften, sondern sind selbst
aktive Teilnehmer im Theorieentwicklungsprozess der Einzelwissenschaften.
In dieser Perspektive ist das Ziel der Wissenschaftsphilosophie nicht nur
zu verstehen, was Wissenschaft ist und nach Möglichkeit den
Wissenschaftsbetrieb methodologisch zu verbessern. Vielmehr soll auch ein
inhaltlicher Beitrag zu den einzelwissenschaftlichen Fragestellungen
geliefert werden” (Reydon/Hoyningen-Huene
2011: 136, see Hansson 2008: 472-483). These considerations are described
by Thomas A. C. Reydon and Paul Hoyningen-Huene under the subheading
“Participatory Philosophy of Science”.
The second position, philosophy-with mode, is summed up as follows: “Other
authors have a more ambitious goal: in their opinion, the philosophy of science
should also seek to produce scientific knowledge. Here, the philosophy of
science becomes an interdisciplinary enterprise and the philosopher of science a
researcher who participates in the knowledge production process of the
individual sciences and continues this process in areas where the individual
sciences themselves do not occur”, my translation: "Andere Autoren haben ein
ambitionierteres Ziel: Ihrer Meinung nach sollte die Wissenschaftsphilosophie
ebenfalls anstreben, wissenschaftliches Wissen zu produzieren. Die
Wissenschaftsphilosophie wird hier zu einem interdisziplinären Unternehmen und
der Wissenschaftsphilosoph zu einem Forscher, der selbst am
Wissensproduktionsprozess der Einzelwissenschaften teilnimmt und diesen Prozess
in den Bereichen weiter fortsetzt, wo die Einzelwissenschaften selbst nicht
auftreten“ (Reydon/Hoyningen-Huene:
136, see also 140-141).
Mario Bunge is also committed to a close collaboration between philosophy and
individual science: “Now a philosophy of x [x stands for any single science]
should match x rather than be at variance with x, for only then will it be able
to (a) give an adequate (true) description of x, (b) suggest fruitful avenues
for the conduct of inquiry in x, and (c) participate competently and effectively
in philosophical controversies in or about x. We call these the conditions of
adequacy and fertility (…). But what does ‘match’ mean in this context? Loosely
speaking, a philosophy Px of x matches x if Px shares the ‘spirit’ or ‘attitude’
of x, deals with philosophical issues raised by the actual practice of x, and
makes use of scientific findings to construct and check its own hypotheses” (Bunge 1996: 10).
Logical positivism and Erlanger constructivism can be seen as
philosophical schools working in the philosophy-of mode. The overwhelming
majority of twentieth-century philosophers of science, on the other hand,
have always explained their considerations using the example of a single
science, with physics predominating (Popper 2005 [1934],
Kuhn 1976 [1962],
Feyerabend 1986 [1975],
Lakatos 1978). In the
second half of the 20th century, there was a turn to biology (Salmon
1989,
Vollmer 2002 [1975]), to
medicine (Wieland
1986), in some cases to the social sciences (Topitsch
1967,
Adorno 1976
[1969],
Acham 1983,
Bodammer 1987, Salmon
1992,
Braun/Saam 2015) and the
technical sciences (Bunge
1996, Poser 2008a,
Kornwachs 2012). In
the following, I will briefly describe how I understand, have pursued and
continue to operate a participatory methodology of science based on the
example of political science.
B. Participatory scientific methodology using the example of political
science
My criticism is directed at the mainstream of the sciences, especially
political science, meaning both the scientists and the interpretivists. A
practical (normative, pragmatic and technical) discourse that satisfies
current logical-analytic reasoning is not possible with either the
scientistic or the interpretive methodology, because it requires a
practical (normative, pragmatic and technical) and not a reductionist
methodology.
In particular, using the example of the European Union and social
security, I have explained, explicated, clarified, reconstructed, newly
developed or further developed scientific tools (concepts and
methodological approaches) in accordance with my motto, “combining
tradition and progress”. Thus, I practice scientific theory as a
participatory methodology of science based on concrete questions within
political science (Lauer
1993 and
1998).
In my opinion, methodological questions can only be adequately addressed
within a participatory scientific methodology. This first requires dealing
with philosophical questions (Lauer
2013). Secondly, it examines the concrete axiological, conceptual,
epistemological, methodological and ontological considerations within a
discipline. I do so using the example of political science (Lauer
1997). Third, applying concrete methodology to concrete, paradigmatic
examples, I have elaborated this most extensively on the example of social
security (Lauer
1998).
C. The need to treat axiological, epistemic, methodological and ontological
questions ideally on ten vertical and three horizontal levels
“Attempts are made to differentiate the levels of abstraction more strongly
than is the case in most American representations, where arguments from the
meta-theoretical, theoretical, methodological and research-technical levels are
often juxtaposed. It should not be concealed that this attempt occasionally has
something artificial about it”, my translation: „Es wird versucht, die Abstraktionsebenen stärker zu sondern, als dies in den
meisten amerikanischen Darstellungen der Fall ist, bei denen Argumente der
meta-theoretischen, theoretischen, methodologischen und forschungstechnischen
Ebene häufig unvermittelt nebeneinander stehen. Es sei nicht verschwiegen, daß
dieser
Versuch gelegentlich auch etwas Künstliches an sich hat“ (von Beyme
2000 [1972]: 7).
Following the approach of Klaus Gustav Heinrich von Beyme, the aim here
is to separate the different methodological levels of scientific discourse.
I wish to show the complexity and diversity of scientific discourses and
their methodology, in particular by identifying the implicit assumptions
and prerequisites, which are found mainly in the choice of scientific tools
as well as in the presupposed philosophical (axiological, epistemological,
methodological and ontological) foundations.
The distinction between different levels of scientific theory certainly
has something artificial about it and can only be idealized. Nevertheless,
it is made because it is not only of didactic interest, but is central to
both scientific analysis and the evaluation of scientific results. The
distinction between ten vertical and three horizontal levels forms, as it
were, the intellectual overview, an orientation or a topography of
scientific methodology (logical geography,
Ryle
2009 [1949]; orientation in the thinking or topography of reason,
Kant 1977 [1786]).
The ten vertical levels also form the outline, following which almost all
subsequent chapters and charts are constructed. In this work, all ten
levels of scientific discourse are systematically represented (Chart
1).
A horizontal structure is further added to this vertical structure. In
the first place, there are structural differences between
empirical-interpretive (descriptive), empirical-explanatory and
empirical-prognostic and practical methodologies, and secondly, these
methodologies complement each other (Chart
2).
This monograph seeks to identify three distinct methodological
traditions between which methodological incommensurability can be
identified, that is, each methodology has different axiological, epistemic,
methodological and ontological presuppositions or assumptions. On the one
hand, a fundamental difference between an empirical (descriptive,
explanatory and prognostic) methodology (Chart
6) and a practical (normative, pragmatic and technical) methodology (Chart
7) should be pointed out. Within empirical methodology, there are
differences in principle between an interpretative (empirical-descriptive)
(Chart 3) and a scientistic (empirical-explanatory and
empirical-prognostic) methodology (Chart
4). All three methodologies can be found in the
second chart).
It does not make sense to speak of different paradigms within political
science, because they do not involve general incommensurability. The
methodological incommensurability does not lead to irreconcilable
discontinuities that prevent meaningful coexistence. But this is exactly what
should be the case when one speaks of different paradigms, as the Kuhn narrative
urges. On the contrary, a practical methodology is necessarily dependent on the
results generated by an empirical (descriptive, explanatory and prognostic)
methodology. To generate political knowledge, therefore, one needs all three
methodologies: first, the empirical-descriptive methodology to describe visible
political phenomena, then the empirical-explanatory and prognostic methodology
to explain the invisible causal relation of these phenomena and make predictions
about the future. Only with a genuinely practical (normative, pragmatic and
technical) methodology can political standardization and regulations be
justified. A practical political science that seeks to justify realistic
regulatory proposals and not alien dystopias or utopias is dependent on the
knowledge that has been developed with the help of empirical-descriptive and
empirical-explanatory methodologies (Chart
9).
|
1.3.3 Value issues within
political science and practical methodology |
|
The possibilities and limitations of practical methodologies are a particular
focus of my scientific interests. The search for scientific answers to practical
political questions forms the core of my work. I acknowledge empirical
(descriptive, explanatory and prognostic) answers, but my claim is to formulate
practical (normative, pragmatic, technical) answers with practical tools
(concepts, sentences, theories, logics, arguments, methods and methodological
approaches). It is necessary to use existing scientific tools, to develop some
of them further and to discover and justify new ones.
The possibilities and limits of two practical methodologies should
therefore be presented and critically evaluated. Both the practical
methodology of the scientistic scientists (normative rational choice
theory) and of the phronetic perestroikans (applied phronesis) will be
evaluated. Unfortunately, little attention has been paid to practical
methodology within the linguistic-interpretive methodology, although a
practical, problem-driven research (problem-based research) is
vigorously demanded (Green/Shapiro 1994,
Shapiro
2005, Schram 2003 und
2005). The phronetic
perestroikans, as one of several interpretive schools, not only demand
problem-driven research, but have also used applied phronesis to formulate
a methodological approach for how to concretely implement this kind of
research.
The aim of modern science is to enrich human life (Bacon
1990 [1620]: 173, 81. aphorism, part 1). Scientistic scientists believe that one
can make “inversions of causal statements” (Weber
1973d [1917]: 529 [491]) or “mere inversions of the basic schema of scientific
explanation” (Popper
1981 [1972]: 353). Both are only possible because there is an equivalence
between causality and action (Bacon
1990 [1620], 3rd aphorism). Only under this assumption can recognition (theory)
be converted into action (practice), i.e. into social technology. Practical
problems can therefore be solved through the inversion of causal statements,
because true knowledge and effective action are equivalent (Bacon
1990 [1620]: 286, 4th aphorism, part 2).
The scientistic establishment not only believes that normative rational
choice theory offers an adequate practical methodology, but also that it is
the best practical-normative methodology (Hardin
2011 [2009]).
The phronetic perestroikans question the problem orientation of the
scientistic scientists and want to use an applied phronesis to revolutionize
political science and to help it regain more public relevance: the titles of
their works – “Making Social Science Matter: Why Social Inquiry Fails and How It
Can Succeed Again” (Flyvbjerg
2001), “Making Political Science Matter” (Schram/ Caterino
2006), and “Real Social Science. Applied Phronesis” (Flyvbjerg/Landman/Schram
2012a) – indicate the program.
Weber distinguishes between empirical and practical social science. He
notes the distinction between theoretical and practical philosophy that has
existed since antiquity only indirectly, in a footnote in which he
emphatically emphasizes the work of the logicians of neo-Kantianism (Weber 2011 [1904]: 50). In his methodological writings, Weber’s main concern is
the possibilities and limitations of an empirical science. The limits he
worked out for empirical sciences are generally still accepted by the
empirical-oriented scientistic scientists today.
On the other hand, the perestroikans, as well as most interpretivists,
reject a separation between is and ought (Sein and Sollen). Furthermore, they
claim that the axiological values of the researchers and the explorers almost
necessarily influence research as guiding interests (Habermas
1968c).
Further important goals of this work concerning value questions include,
firstly, a detailed presentation of the axiological arguments and their
influence on scientific results. Secondly, the critique of the philosophers of
technology (Bunge 1967b,
Kornwachs
2008 and
2012,
Poser 2001) is explained.
An inversion of causal statements that Maximilian Carl Emil Weber and Karl
Raimund Popper is still considered unproblematic. Third, the need for a
practical (normative, pragmatic, and technical) methodology that differs at ten
levels from an empirical (descriptive, explanatory and prognostic) methodology
is explained.
The end goal is to justify the possibility and necessity of a practical
political science, and also of a practical social science, which builds on the
scientific-theoretical distinction pointed out by Weber. This practical
methodology establishes a practical political science that is also in the
Aristotelian tradition, but has little in common with the practical political
science of Wilhelm Hennis
(1963). Neither the normative rational choice approach of the scientists, nor
the applied phronesis of the perestroikans, nor the topics favored by Hennis are
rejected, but they form only very small parts of a much broader practical
(normative, pragmatic and technical) methodology.
There are several models for how to shape the relationship between practical
politics and political science. Not a few scientistic scientists lean towards a
technocratic model in which science has the last word. The lack of democratic
legitimacy in this approach is immediately striking. On the other hand, while
the decisionist model has democratic legitimacy, it is lacking in factual
expertise.
Jürgen
Habermas
(1968b [1963]) proposed a pragmatic model that combines the advantages of the
technocratic and the decision-making model and overcomes the disadvantages of
both. In many handbooks on political consulting (Falk/Rehfeld/Römmele/Thunert 2006,
Heidelberger Akademie der
Wissenschaften 2006,
Bröchler/Schützeichel
2008) this model is not only discussed, but preferred by most scientists
as well as by the phronetic perestroikans. It is also used in practical
politics; the EU Commission for example also resorts to the pragmatic model and
argues for a democratization of expertise (democratising expertise) and a
scientification of democracy (expertising democracy) (EU-Commission 2001a,
EU-Commission 2001b,
EU-Commission 2002).
Due to the fact that practical politics and science have different functional
logics, i.e. have different tasks and have to comply with different requirements
and criteria, the pragmatic model of political consulting in the end can meet
neither democratic nor scientific standards. For reasons of principle, science
can only justify hypothetical knowledge (Chart
9), but neither make definite or binding decisions nor assume liability for
their consequences. Democratic institutions can do just that: make binding and
definitive decisions, and at the same time be liable for the consequences, i.e.
assume legal responsibility. Therefore, I advocate a complementary model of
political consulting in which each subsystem performs its tasks as well as
possible (Chart 12,
Chart 11).
|
The introduction provides a general lead-in to the topic as well as
an overview of the most important questions. The second and third chapters
present the actual "Methodenstreit" between scientistic scientists and
perestroikans within political science at the beginning of the 21st
century.
The axiological, epistemological, methodological and ontological
arguments in political science are characterized not only by the complexity
of the topics they contain, but also by confusion, mutual criticism and
misunderstandings of all kinds, just as those in the positivism dispute (Adorno
et al., 1976). To avoid confusion and misunderstandings, the
"Methodenstreit" is dealt with in two chapters, at the risk of redundancies
and repetitions.
First, the second chapter discusses the most important issues that
characterize this dispute. This is followed by an explication of terminology,
which is necessary for the structuring of the questions and controversies, so
that a factual discussion becomes possible. The scientistic scientists
(naturalists, causal reductionists, (neo) positivists, disciplined political
scientists; 3rd chart),
who are oriented towards the natural sciences and apply a logical-mathematical
research methodology, are introduced first. At the conclusion of the second
chapter, the competing methodological tradition, which is oriented towards the
humanities and cultural studies and uses a linguistic-interpretive methodology,
is considered using the example of the phronetic perestroikans (Chart
4). They represent the latest major rebellion against the scientistic
establishment – and not against the mainstream, as is generally claimed. The
terms “establishment” and “perestroikans” are also explained here.
The second chapter is primarily about the Kuhn narrative, that
is, the storyline of the methodological war. This is antagonistic
and can convince dramaturgically and rhetorically, but it not only stands
in the way of an adequate scientific debate but has for decades been
contributing to a considerable extent to this counterproductive
methodological war. In the reduction of complexity, Ockham’s razor is used
so boldly that of the actual opponents only cardboard figures are left. The
economy principle (principle of parsimony), first formulated by Wilhelm of
Ockham (1288-1347), in this case calls for the economic use of scientific
philosophical assumptions.
The methodological war, known as the "Methodenstreit", can
therefore only be ended by first working with other terms. Secondly, if one
reduces the other position to a handful of caricatured theses, important
assumptions are omitted or distorted. A more nuanced presentation of
political methodology, i.e. an ad fontes reconstruction from
original sources, is inevitable because of its complexity. This is what the
next chapter will do.
The third chapter is the most important and
comprehensive part of this work. It undertakes a differentiation and a
nuancing between terms bordering on pedantry. The factual, philosophical
(axiological, epistemological, methodological and ontological)
differences and some similarities between the scientistic
establishment and the phronetic perestroikans, as well as my own
statements, are examined in more detail on ten levels (Chart
1). In addition to these distinctions made on the vertical plane, above
all for epistemic reasons, three distinctions are made on the horizontal
level for axiological and ontological reasons (Chart
2). Only with such differentiations can one reasonably do justice to
the complexity of these issues, as explained elsewhere (Lauer
2013 and
1997).
Only a few answers to these questions can be discussed. The aim is to
provide an overview of the manifold relationships between axiological,
epistemological, methodological and ontological questions or a logical
geography of political methodology (Chart
2).
The fourth chapter presents a summary of the results and the main
theses. The introduction started with some reflections on the importance of the
methodology, and the summary asks whether the "Methodenstreit" is an expression
of an identity crisis or a sign of relevance and vitality.
The fifth chapter contains an outline of political methodology. The
outlook is intended to provide a brief overview of political science methodology
in general and, in particular, an overview of the methodology of practical
political science. Here, ways to overcome the deficits of political
methodology in general as well as of practical methodology in particular are
identified (Chart 10). A practical political science as supplementing an empirical
(descriptive, explanatory and prognostic) political science (Chart
6) with a practical (normative, pragmatic and technical) methodology (Chart
7, Chart 13) is, in my opinion, the appropriate place to discuss practical political
issues. A practical methodology can justify a practical social science
(Weber 2011 [1904]) and thus also a practical political science (Chart
8, Chart 9).
|
The citations in this essay and in the references have several
special features:
- The citation first indicates the year of the edition used and the
original year of publication in square brackets. For classic works, the
original year of publication (not the year of publication of the first
German translation) is always stated in square brackets after the year
of publication of the edition used.
- The page number refers to information on the used edition.
Exceptions to this are due to edition conditions. In classics such as
Aristotle, Plato, Immanuel Kant or Maximilian Carl Emil Weber, the page
numbers of basic editions are also recorded in square brackets. A
special citation is also appropriate for the works of Ludwig Josef
Johann Wittgenstein. In the Philosophical Investigations, the paragraph
is indicated instead of the page number, while in the Tractatus
logico-philosophicus only the number of the sentence is shown.
- The indication of the edition is omitted in the text, whereas it is
indicated in the bibliography. For online articles, the URL as well as
the last date of access of the website are listed.
- As a rule, the first names of all authors are mentioned, provided
they could be determined.
I have also been publishing scientific papers on the Internet for years,
and a number of projects are constantly being developed as “works in
progress”. I use extensive material from these projects. These projects are
referenced as follows:
- Internet project ongoing since 1997: Scientific Political
Consulting. Part II: Methodology of Practical Political Science. URL:
praktische-politikwissenschaft.de. Referenced in the text as “Lauer
1997”.
- Internet project ongoing since 1998: The potentials of the German
social model. Proposals for a consistent and complementary development.
URL: soziale-sicherheit.de. Referenced in the text as “Lauer
1998”.
- Internet project ongoing since 2013: Scientific Political
Consulting. Part I: Methodology of empirical and practical science.
URL: praktische-wissenschaften.de. Referenced in the text as “Lauer
2013”.
A self-citation is avoided because it would be very reader-unfriendly.
The necessary URL information would make the text illegible, as the
projects that are being developed are published in HTML format and not in
PDF format. These projects have not yet been published in print.
|
Linear text has a fixed structure in which the reader moves from the
beginning to the end of the text (from left to right and from top to bottom). If
the text is in digital form, the contents are in a file. The text is linear in
all print forms. Hypertext or transient text has no rigid
structure and is usually not contained in just one file but is spread across
several files. The reader has the opportunity to jump from one place in the text
to another via links or references and to return to the original position.
Hypertext refers to connections between documents that have the purpose of
explaining terms and pointing to other documents. Image and graphics, audio and
video can also be integrated.
Although possibilities for fast navigation within the text have also
been developed for books (e.g. tables of contents, person and subject
registers), hypertext makes this much easier. This not only makes reading
easier for the reader, but also facilitates the evaluation and thus the
understanding of complex relations and contexts. An HTML version of this
monograph can be found on the Internet at the following URL:
http://www.lauer.biz/methodenstreit/index-en.htm
|
|
|